President Obama’s former
Administrator of the White House Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs
Cass Sunstein has recently penned a derisive statist column entitled “How to Spot a Paranoid Libertarian.” In the
column, Sunstein attacks all those on the right who sound the alarm against gun
control, progressive taxation, environmental protection, and health care reform
as well as those on the left who sound the alarm against violations of the
separation of church and state and overzealous privacy violating anti-terrorism
efforts.
While Sunstein quotes novelist Joseph Heller’s truism: “Just
because you’re paranoid doesn’t mean they aren’t after you” and acknowledges
that “paranoid libertarians” might sometimes “draw attention to genuine risks,”
he claims that “paranoia isn’t a good foundation for public policy, even if it
operates in freedom’s name.” In other words, pay no attention to all the
dangerous unconstitutional abuses that civil libertarians have warned about in
the past. A broken clock is right twice a day, and just because those crazy
persons are sometimes right, it does not mean that they are not crazy. It also
does not mean that anyone should really pay attention to what they have to say.
So confident is Sunstein of
himself that he does not bother to even attempt to present well reasoned
arguments against “paranoid libertarianism.” Instead, he merely lists five
characteristics. Apparently, he must believe that these characteristics are so
dubious that it goes without saying that behind them lies paranoia and not
reason. Despite claiming to distinguish “paranoid libertarianism” from
libertarianism in general, if one removes the allegedly paranoid
characteristics of “paranoid libertarianism,” whatever view remains can hardly
be called libertarianism.
1.Wildy exaggerated sense or
risks
According to Sunstein, “paranoid libertarians” wildly exaggerate the
risks of government activity such as gun control or surveillance. “Paranoid
libertarians” believe—whether they have evidence or not—that the government “will
inevitably use its authority so as to jeopardize civil liberties and perhaps
democracy itself.”
For a legal scholar and former
law school professor, Sunstein is shockingly naïve when it comes to the state.
Even more surprising is that he does not seem to understand that the entire
basis for and structure of the American Constitutional Republicanism is the
truism that the state is dangerous. The reason that the Founders decided that
they had to chain down government with Constitutional limitations, checks, and
balances and with the Bill of Rights was that they understood the inevitability
that governments tend to abuse their powers and that this abuse invariably
violated the natural rights of the people.
History is nothing if not the
chronicle of authoritarian governments violating natural rights. From ancient
tyrannical kings to the totalitarian governments of the twentieth and
twenty-first centuries, human beings have historically had much to fear from
their rulers. The state has been such an enemy of individualism and freedom
that suspicion concerning government power is clearly the rational default
position to hold. This is true even concerning the United
States government. The government has used its
authority to defend the institution of slavery, attempt to commit genocide
against American Indians, imprison Japanese-Americans in concentration camps
during World War II, spy on American citizens almost ceaselessly without
probable cause for decades, etc.
2. Presumption of bad faith on
the part of government officials
Sunstein also criticizes
“paranoid libertarians” for holding the belief that the motivations of
government officials cannot be trusted. For example, he claims that they
believe that the “real” motivations for any restrictions on gun ownership must
be that the government officials behind such regulations seek to disarm the
American public.
The truth of the matter is that
government officials often do have motivations that cannot be trusted. In a
democratic system, elected officials often have to mask their true intentions
in order to win elections. It is by now a truism that politicians lie,
therefore, it becomes rational to mistrust the intentions of politicians. While
it is not always possible to ascertain the true motivations of government
officials, there is a strong enough correlation between zealous government
officials and harms to civil liberties that it is reasonable to always be wary
of those wielding state power. Even when the intentions are not specifically
malicious, these intentions are often characterized by indifference motivated
ultimately by greed. In exchange for campaign contributions—which often
function as nothing more than bribes—many elected officials simply do what
their patrons—corporations, unions, PACs, etc.—demand. And when the motivations
of government officials are honorable, this often produces the worst tyranny.
The humanitarian paternalism of the Progressive Era laid down ample blacktop on
the way to Hell.
3. A sense of past, present or
future victimization
Sunstein says of “paranoid
libertarians” that they “tend to believe that as individuals or as members of
specified groups, they are being targeted by the government, or will be
targeted imminently, or will be targeted as soon as officials have the
opportunity to target them.”
Very little needs to be said
about this claim. Following the Snowden revelations, the government has openly
admitted that the NSA is targeting everyone. The federal government has long
since given up on worrying about the Fourth Amendment and probable cause, and as
a result, the NSA’s dragnet collection of metadata means that every American
citizen is a target of the government.
4. An indifference to trade-offs
What Sunstein really means is
that the belief that natural rights are inalienable is unreasonable. He
attempts to stigmatize the view that liberty is “the overriding if not the only
value” and criticizes those who do believe this tenet of American government as
being inflexible and narrow-minded by believing that “it is unreasonable and
weak to see relevant considerations on both sides.”
Sunstein believes that everything
is negotiable, and therefore, those who are unwilling to compromise on
everything are extremists and possibly even mentally imbalanced. There are
clearly matters on which it is reasonable to compromise. If I want to buy a
used paperback novel from you at a flea market for $1 and you want $2 for it,
it’s not unreasonable for us to “meet halfway” and make a deal to exchange
$1.50 for the book. However, there is nothing unreasonable about being
unwilling to compromise on one’s natural rights. If you wish to kill me, and I
wish to keep living, it is not rational for me to accept a trade-off by which
you merely beat me half to death. If you wish to enslave me, but I would prefer
to remain free, it is not rational for me to accept a trade-off by which I will
become your slave for only 12 hours a day. If you wish to steal from me, and I
wish to keep my possessions, it is not rational for me to accept a trade-off by
which you only steal half of all that I own.
Sunstein laments that “paranoid
libertarians tend to dismiss the benefits of other measures that they despise,
including gun control and environmental regulation.” However, this is to make
the assumption that such measures actually have benefits. If gun regulations
had value, then one would expect cities with strong gun control laws such as Chicago
to have little or no gun violence. This, as has been shown ad nauseum, is not
the case. If, by “environmental regulation,” Sunstein means carbon taxes or
other draconian measures aimed at ending “climate change,” then there is also
no benefit to be expected by such a trade-off because evidence is mounting that
“climate change” is simply not a genuine phenomenon. In essence, Sunstein seems
to mean that one is mentally imbalanced if one is unwilling to allow his or her
inalienable rights to be at least partially alienated and that one is equally
imbalanced if he or she is unwilling to make serious concessions to government
regulations based upon propositions that are either debunked or unproven.
5. Enthusiasm for slippery-slope
arguments
It is this final characteristic
of “paranoid libertarianism” which best sums up Sunstein’s worldview and the
libertarian worldview that he opposes. According to Sunstein:
The fear is that if
government is allowed to take an apparently modest step today, it will take far
less modest steps tomorrow, and on the next day, freedom itself will be in
terrible trouble. Modest and apparently reasonable steps must be resisted as if
they were the incarnation of tyranny itself.
Slippery slope arguments can be and are sometimes abused. In
The Breakfast Club, when after Mr. Vernon
allows Andrew Clark to get up from his seat, and John Bender quips: “Hey, how
come Andrew gets to get up? If he gets up, we'll all get up, it'll be anarchy,”
the line is funny because of the absurd slippery slope reasoning that is
mocked. From the point of view of deductive reasoning, a slippery slope
argument is fallacious because there is no way to assert with certainty that
the feared consequence will result. For example, it would be fallacious to
assert that it is deductively certain that total gun confiscation will result
from a ban on convicted felons owning assault rifles. However, when a slippery
slope argument is instead employed as a form of inductive reasoning, and there
is strong evidence that the feared consequence is likely to result, then such
reasoning is logical. For example, it is well known that tyrannical regimes
have often curtailed freedoms gradually, slowly killing their citizens’ rights
the way that a frog is slowly killed in a pot of boiling water. The Nazis did
not begin the “final solution” of the Holocaust immediately after assuming
power. Along the way to complete tyranny, the Nazis passed the Reichstag Fire Decree,
the Enabling Act,
the Nuremberg Laws,
etc.When one acts as if a law that violates natural rights does not matter,
then soon one will find the nation on the road to totalitarianism. The slowly boiling
frog does not notice that it is boiling, but when human beings do realize it,
the rational thing is to get out of the water rather than assume that the fact
that the water is beginning to get hot does not mean that it will continue to
get hotter until it is dangerously hot.
No comments:
Post a Comment